Sunday, November 6, 2022

The tao is of its own accord.

The mind works of its own accord.

Some say that the mind makes a heaven of hell or a hell of heaven.

Despite our best efforts, our mind may refuse to recover from its illness.

Despite the best environment a person may find himself in, the mind may fall sick like the body does without reason.

For it is often not up to him how the mind should think and feel.

His bad personality is often a reflection of his unhappiness.

If it is the unhappy environment thats bothering him, he can simply choose to change it.

If he is unable to change it, he will always be unhappy and his mind will fall ill.

He can only pray, with his prayers unanswered.

If it is a given that he will only suffer, he can only survive in a philosophical way.

But that is the most arduous path of all.

It is preferable that he finds happiness by putting an end to his misery.



Tuesday, May 17, 2022

“DETERMINISTIC KNOWLEDGE FOR HUMAN AND MACHINE INTELLIGENCE AS INCONGRUENT COUNTERPARTS IN SUPER-RELATIONAL CONTEXT”

1. The incongruent counterparts

2. Deterministic knowledge

3. Dennett’s “Derrida-like” interpretation of our intelligence

4. Movement as an actualization of a metaphysical possibility

5. Knowledge-in-hindsight for artificial intelligence

6. Super-relationalism contra special relativity 

 

ABSTRACT

The purpose of this writing is to provide through extrapolation from Kant’s incongruent counterparts a new metaphysical framework for a valid distinction between human intelligence and machine intelligence that finds its root in conventional functionalism. Under this framework, this writing also analyzes the implications of both determinism and indeterminism and their relations to human reason. Moreover, Jacques Derrida’s deconstructionism and Daniel Dennett’s “trivial” determinism are challenged under the same framework, along with providing an alternative view that attempts to settle the issue of absolute/relational space between Newton and Leibniz. Also, after introducing a peculiar philosophical calculus in accordance with special relativity that ultimately provides a basis for “non-trivial” determinism, the writing concludes by noting that Hegelian philosophy is necessarily the latent holistic framework for scientific investigation regardless of scientists’ awareness of it.

 

1. The incongruent counterparts

Immanuel Kant devised the concept of incongruent counterparts in order to decide on the issue of absolute/relational space. According to the absolute theory of space, even if there were only a single body and nothing else, the body could move by itself. Meanwhile, the relational theory asserts the body could not move at all because motion can be defined only in relation to other bodies.

Kant, however, proposes to put aside the element of motion from the issue and argues as follows. If the relational theory is correct, there can be no difference between a world where only a right hand exists (“RH world”) and a world where only a left hand exists (“LH world”).

More specifically, the physical attributes of the left hand as thought to be by an imaginary observer whose view is restricted by the LH world cannot be any different from those of the right hand as thought to be by an imaginary observer whose view is restricted by the RH world. That is, each world is restricted by its respective one-world perspective. (A one-world or two-world perspective is not so much our philosophical view as our physical understanding of an either world or both worlds.)

However, this relational view must be wrong since it is obvious from an outsider’s view (two-world perspective) that these worlds are different. A relationalist’s response to this argument is that the two-world perspective through which the two worlds appear distinct can be established only because of the pre-established existence of the two worlds. Let us specify the following terms for further discussion.

Absolutism: The two-world perspective exists prior to the establishment of the two worlds.

Relationalism: The two-world perspective exists due to the establishment of the two worlds.

Neo-relationalism*: The two-world perspective emerges through dependence on a relational context of the two worlds, in which case such emergence (which may be necessary or contingent) was already immanent in the cosmos.

Let us posit the following different worlds:

(LH1) A right hand cannot enter into an (relationalistic) LH world, which does not allow emergence of the two-world perspective.

(LH2-1) A right hand can enter into an LH world, and if it does it is perceived no differently than the existing left hand. This world does not allow emergence of the two-world perspective and is neither relationalistic nor absolutistic.

(LH2-2) A right hand can enter into an (relationalistic) LH world, and if it does, the existing dimension of the LH world is elevated to that of an absolutistic world, thereby enabling perception or postulation of the right hand. The two-world perspective emergence was immanent in this world.

(LH2-3) When the existing dimension of an (relationalistic) LH world is elevated to that of an absolutistic world, a right hand can enter into and be perceived differently in the LH world. The two-world perspective emergence was immanent in this world.

(RH1) A left hand cannot enter into an (absolutistic) RH world. However, in the RH world, the existence of a left hand can be postulated whether it exists or not outside of the RH world. In this world, the two-world perspective holds with no possibility of its substantiation. Also, the absolutistic characteristic of the world might have been made possible by the presence of other LH worlds in the cosmos.

(RH2) A left hand can enter into an (absolutistic) RH world. Also, in the RH world, the existence of a left hand can be postulated in advance prior to such entry. In this world, the two-world perspective holds with a possibility of its substantiation. Also, the absolutistic characteristic of the world might have been made possible by the presence of other LH worlds in the cosmos.

2. Deterministic knowledge

We can discuss the issue of determinism by assuming two deterministic universes and analogizing them to two incongruent counterparts.

More specifically:

(i) A prototype world as a genuine world like ours

(ii) An emulation world that represents through functionalism everything that there is about the prototype world

The discussion is based on the following definitions.

Deterministic knowledge*(D knowledge): The totality of all the verbal descriptions of all the past, present, and future events of a deterministic universe, the metaphysical presence of the said totality being such that it coincides with every time point of the universe.

Knowledge-in-hindsight*(H knowledge): The totality of all the verbal descriptions of all the events of a universe ranging from the beginning to a particular time point, the metaphysical presence of the said totality being such that it coincides only with the particular time point

Metaphysically open deterministic universe*: A deterministic universe where there is a metaphysical sense in assuming a case in which a cognitive agent has access to the D knowledge of the universe.

Metaphysically open indeterministic universe*: A universe for which no D knowledge exists in principle and whose history is built up only in the form of H knowledge, the universe being such that there is a metaphysical sense in assuming a case in which a cognitive agent of the past has access to the H knowledge of the future.

Let us assume that the prototype and emulation worlds are metaphysically open deterministic universes, by considering that it is only when we tolerate a possibility that the content of D knowledge can enter as an input into the minds of particular agents in both worlds that the distinction between the two worlds is revealed.

If the D knowledge were provided to the prototype world, it would have been received as a previously unavailable input by a cognitive agent of the world and lead to the generation of a novel output that is contextually relevant to the world (that is characterized by RH1 and RH2 and whose duality is tolerated through metaphysicalism). Such a world is a non-trivially deterministic* world, in which the D knowledge is causally subsequent deterministic knowledge, the presence of which is causally subsequent to but temporally coincides with the origin of the world. This world requires that a metaphysical perspective from which everything seems decided emerge instantaneously together with the beginning of the world. Put differently, the D knowledge generated as such is an earliest possible reflection of everything that was bound to occur. Also, the immanence of a novel output in response to the D knowledge is established in a metaphysical sense, although the novel output itself may not have been predetermined. However, if the D knowledge were also deducible -- as well as extant through a metaphysical configuration -- through a transcendental calculus beyond the realm of our universe, this would also indicate the calculability of the novel output itself, which would point to the metaphysical presence of another form of D knowledge pertaining to the original D knowledge and so on.

On the other hand, if the D knowledge were provided to the emulation world (that is characterized by LH1 and LH2-1 and whose duality is tolerated through metaphysicalism) it would have been merely reduced to one of the then available inputs and lead to a corresponding output. Such a world is a trivially deterministic* world, in which the D knowledge is causally precedent deterministic knowledge, the presence of which causally precedes the origin of the world. That is, this world is that which was constructed by design under the precedent D knowledge.

The distinction between subsequent and precedent deterministic knowledge is important because the conception of precedent D knowledge is implausible in a metaphysically open, non-trivially deterministic world.

Admittedly, absorption of D knowledge CANNOT physically occur in either deterministic world (RH1 or LH1), because by definition it is rigidly deterministic. Therefore, the distinction should be understood only in a metaphysical sense.

Unfortunately, to logical positivists and Popperian thinkers, such an idea will sound outlandish and appear as vacant as the ancient texts of I-Ching. Another limitation of my proposal is that it does not explain our unconsciousness. The workings and progress of the human psyche are so complex that it cannot be said that the only difference between human consciousness and naïvely functionalistic machine intelligence is that the former has a latent capacity to creatively interpret an “otherworldly but comprehensible” input and the latter does not.

(Meanwhile, “otherworldly and incomprehensible” subject matter may belong in the realm of Kantian things-in-themselves and be behind emergent phenomena. Metaphysical knowledge is -- as the “totality of facts” according to Wittgenstein -- simply an ethereal manifestation of the noumena relative to human reason. We may justifiably speculate the existence of or even describe the details of parallel universes through natural science (RH1), but we cannot know anything about, but can only posit, things-in-themselves themselves.)

 

3. Dennett’s “Derrida-like” interpretation of our intelligence

“There is nothing outside the text.”

The above quote is from Jacques Derrida, and I think it succinctly shows the mightiness of language as, arguably, the only means of human thought. Derrida-led postmodernists may even go so far as to argue that there is no such thing as “meaning,” and that if there is ever to be such a thing as meaning, it must be a byproduct of differ”a”nce (cf. relationalism). It is as if signifiers took precedence over the signifieds. However, common sense tells us that no language use would be possible in the absence of meaning. When Derrida asserts that nothing can exist outside the text, he does not know or only subconsciously knows that meaning exists in relation to the text (cf. neo-relationalism). To put it in a Zizekian way, Hegelians do not know that they are anti-Hegelians (in that they are unaware they must break free from dogmatic Hegelianism to be true Hegelians) and anti-Hegelians do not know that they are Hegelians (in that they are unaware Deleuze’s neurotic opposition to Hegelianism paradoxically helps to achieve Hegelianism). If they do, their knowledge is only subconscious.

To be sure, my claim that deconstructionist philosophy contradicts itself since it implicitly operates with the existence of meaning behind it can be deemed baseless to deconstructionists (cf. LH2-1) since my statement as such could not have been stated if it were not put into language. This radical view reminds me of Daniel Dennett in regards to artificial intelligence. According to him, our mind is no different from a computing machine. Since every conceivable thought can be represented in a conventionally functionalistic way, there is nothing about our mind that escapes algorithms. However, he appears to hastily regard the subsequent constructability of algorithms as proof that the entirety of the human mind is an algorithmic representation and nothing more.

Also, when he argues that determinism is necessary in order for our mind to function properly (because otherwise it would be unclear what it means to have free will), he believes that the future causal chain of events is also predetermined, presumably because the events of our past and present appear rigidly deterministic and their causal connections can be clarified in hindsight.

However, that casual order universally applies to our past/present/future does not necessarily mean that there exists one and only scenario corresponding to them. Our future events will one day be explicable in accordance with our causality-latent understanding, but it is in principle impossible to conclude on the issue of whether the events were predetermined simply based on the notion of causality, provided that our intelligence is distinct over machines’. In other words, the presence of knowledge-in-hindsight does not ensure the presence of deterministic knowledge in general.

In addition, if our future is rigidly deterministic despite our supposed distinction from machines, it is not because of the principle of causality but because of a metaphysical law, which preemptively mirrors, rather than prescribes, our future decisions.

 

4. Movement as an actualization of a metaphysical possibility

The core point of Zeno’s paradox is that if space is continuous as is assumed by Einstein’s relativity, there is no immediate subsequent spatial coordinate next to the origin from which an object departs. However, even if our space and time is continuous, this may cause no contradiction if a particular metaphysical assumption is satisfied. That is, if we assume that a metaphysical possibility of a spatial movement precedes the actual movement and if this is true, the apparent paradox is resolved. More specifically, what appears to us as a movement would be from the metaphysical perspective the endless snapshots of an object in temporally vanishing order that correspond to an infinite number of respective spatial coordinates that exist within a spatial continuum of a finite length. It is not like that the object has to pave its way into a realm of nothingness from the very beginning; rather, the seamless spatial background for its movement is given in advance. Then, its moving trajectory, whose possibility exists in the metaphysical realm, is actualized. This is not an easily graspable idea in an intuitive sense, and that is only natural because if we were able to sense -- which is impossible in the first place -- every one of an infinite number of snapshots, we would not be able to think. Perhaps, provided that spacetime is continuous, it may be that we are able to think at all because our limited mind omits most of the infinite snapshots in a heartbeat. Otherwise, we would spiral into an abyss of new emergence of spatial/temporal coordinates. Therefore, we conclude that our mind thinks (or our perception functions) by discretizing the continuous flux of time. To put it in a different way, the one who sees infinite natural numbers at the same time is not a sentient being.

Also, one way of resolving the dispute between Newton and Leibniz on absolute/relational space is to propose that motion exists as a metaphysical possibility for a single body with respect to other hypothetical objects in an infinite, vacant universe (cf. neo-relationalism). Although it is possible to imagine that the body makes a spatial transition from a particular coordinate to another, no difference can be found between the infinite, vacant universe before the supposed motion of the lone object and the same universe thereafter. Therefore, one may sensibly conclude that the single body’s movement is of an imaginary concept built on our empirical notion of movement in actual space. Nevertheless, it is not principally whether or not other objects exist that decides whether the single body can move. Rather, its potential for motion with respect to the other objects is given in advance, and it is this potential that enables the motion when they come into existence.

 

5. Knowledge-in-hindsight for artificial intelligence

My theory of deterministic knowledge, which was influenced by Gödel (e.g., plugging a Gödel number representing a metamathematical proposition into a variable of the same metamathematical proposition) and Wittgenstein (e.g., a metaphysical world as a “totality of facts”), may provide a relevant discourse with respect to artificial intelligence.

Strong AI proponents argue that human intelligence is realizable in machines, and I believe this is possible if we discover a particular electric configuration that emergent-ly triggers consciousness (LH2-2 and LH2-3).

For our thought experiment, let us name a particular futuristic AI machine (that thinks like humans do) “TARS” and assume that this it is still in its infancy and that all it can do is to think and cannot physically move around yet. Suppose there are three replicas of the TARS prototype: TARS0, TARS1, and TARS2. If TARS0 is put in a confined space and provided with only a limited number of inputs beginning from time point T0 to Tn in a strictly controlled environment, it will have produced a series of outputs that constitute a collection of data, which is an approximation of knowledge-in-hindsight with respect to the remaining TARSs. If such H knowledge is provided to TARS1, after TARS1 was put in the same strictly controlled environment and received the same inputs from T0 to Tn, we can expect that TARS1 will take the H knowledge as a novel input and produce a corresponding novel output. Then, if we provide TARS2 with the same H knowledge that was received by TARS1, in the same manner that we provided it to TARS1, will TARS2 produce the exact same output as TARS1’s? If the two outputs are the same, let us say that this shows “output consistency,” and if not, let us that it shows “output discrepancy.”

In a metaphysically open deterministic universe, output consistency might corroborate the deterministic nature of our thinking process. On the other hand, output discrepancy might indicate that machine intelligence is indeterministic at least relative to ourselves. In either case, it can be said that even our efforts to experimentally determine the nature of a non-trivially deterministic thought process were determined, albeit not predetermined under precedent deterministic knowledge. Perhaps Nietzsche was right when he said that we could willfully practice amor fati despite the fatalistic courses of our lives. It is in this very world that I believe compatibilism is possible.

In a metaphysically open indeterministic universe, output consistency might indicate that although our thought process is deterministic, it is the intrinsic indeterminacy of our physical environment that renders our future indeterministic. On the other hand, output discrepancy might corroborate the indeterministic nature of our thought process. However, in the case of a metaphysically closed world, such a thought experiment might have little meaning.

6. Super-relationalism contra special relativity  

 


 

In order to discuss the implication of special relativity for the concept of knowledge-in-hindsight, let us suppose a case where “B” is moving at the speed of 260,000 km/sec with respect to “A,” who is standing still on earth. Then we deduce the following facts:

 

When 2 sec expires for A from A’s perspective, 1 sec expires for B from A’s perspective.

When 2 sec expires for A from B’s perspective, 4 sec expires for B from B’s perspective.

 

“H knowledge specific to A in a time period from 0 sec to 2 sec in A’s time frame as seen by B” = “H knowledge specific to A in a time period from 0 sec to 2 sec in A’s time frame as seen by A

 

“H knowledge specific to A from 0 sec to 2 sec in A’s time frame as seen by A” is not the same as “H knowledge specific to A from 0 sec to 4 sec in A’s time frame as seen by A”

 

“The totality of H knowledge that pertains to both A and B in a time period from 0 sec to 2 sec in A’s time frame as seen by A”

= (H knowledge specific to B from 0 sec to 1 sec in B’s time frame as seen by B) +

(H knowledge specific to A from 0 sec to 2 sec in A’s time frame as seen by A) +

(H knowledge specific to B from 1 sec to 4 sec in B’s time frame as seen by B) +

(H knowledge specific to A from 2 sec to 8 sec in A’s time frame as seen by A) +…

 

Based on the above knowledge-in-hindsight calculus under special relativity, we conclude that a time lapse from t=0 to t=2 entails the generation of deterministic knowledge in general. However, the time lapse does not necessarily have to be that of 2 seconds. It can be a duration of any seconds or even an infinitesimal second. As such, special relativity appears to be in harmony with the conception of a non-trivially deterministic universe that requires that deterministic knowledge emerge instantaneously along with the beginning of time, supposing that special relativity has been a consistently correct law of physics since the Big Bang.

The current atmosphere of the scientific community is dominated by beliefs in the absence of free will on the basis of well-established arguments for a causal view of the universe. However, one of the most radical ideas about determinism comes from quantum mechanics: Bell’s superdeterminism. Since this view considers every incident of our universe as having been predetermined (perhaps even prior to the beginning of the universe), it appears unclear if there is any significant difference between a physicist’s experimental action and such a trivial physical occurrence as the blowing of the wind or an act of reading this writing. My response to this issue is that it is only through philosophy that the difference is revealed.

Super-relationalism*: A philosophical perspective emerges as an immanent part of the universe in relation to its non-philosophical characteristics if the universe is constructed to allow its emergence, the philosophical perspective identifying itself as being part of the universe in a recursive manner through a perspective over itself and another perspective over the perspective and so on, thereby generating a super-relationalistic context and “nowness” for our consciousness.

The above concept is “but a footnote to Hegel.”

When the alleged feminist philosopher Lao Tzu enunciated “xuán (black) zhī (proceed) yòu (more) xuán (black),” he was not alluding to what the French people call “trous noir (black hole).” Rather, he was more likely characterizing the noumena as becoming ever more mysterious as one delved into it. This property of the noumena, Hegel suggests, is a reflection of our reason.

It is natural for physicists to pay little attention to Hegel unless they have a penchant for philosophy. However, some of them hastily conclude that “philosophy is dead,” while not recognizing the position that they thereby put themselves in. For instance, they do not appear to realize that superdeterminism necessitates, rather than conveniently disposes of, philosophy so as to be considered an object of our speculative investigation. A world governed by superdeterminism that is truly devoid of a naturally arising philosophical perspective does not seek to prove superdeterminism. Superdeterminism (which is questionable) has meaning only when we legitimize ourselves as higher-level observers of the concept (perhaps through employing the notion of “retro-causality”) despite paradoxically seeing ourselves as part of the rigidly predefined universe. Hence, in response to the skeptical scientists, we may speak:

Philosophy makes no contribution to natural science; it is only a necessary feature of the intelligence of our species.

Accordingly, through the successive steps of philosophical reasoning that departed from Kant’s incongruent counterparts to end in Hegel (and start anew therefrom), we conclude that a non-super-relationalistic world is a dead world where no intellectual discourse has any meaning.

 

Written by WesternLight Snacker’s (taoprep.blogspot.com)


* 6. Super-relationalism contra special relativity is based on a flawed understanding of special relativity.